The literature concerned the performing arts, particularly traditional
(mid-Twentieth Century) musical theater, is a mixed bag of impressionistic
opinion, gossip, star-struck hagiography, quasi-history, and, maybe, a little
bit of real experience and understanding. The personal memoirs of Richard
Rodgers and Alan J. Lerner and numerous biographies of them, their collaborators,
and contemporaries provide a “historical” framework for understanding their
art. But there seems to be little in the way of exploration of the “why?” of
their art in the memoirs and biographies. Rodgers did describe some of his
methods, which apparently (apparently?) changed significantly as he moved from
collaboration with Laurence Hart to working with Oscar Hammerstein. Lerner, in
both his memoirs and in his posthumously published tribute to musical theater, explicitly
dodged the issue completely, claiming he did not want to know the “why?” of
musical comedy.
Journalist-critics of musical theater are oriented by necessity
towards immediate reaction to new theatrical works. Commonly, the first review
has been based on a single viewing of a work, rushed by press deadlines. There
is little opportunity for reflection. Particularly since musical theater is a
hybrid of dialogue, music, verse, dance, set, and lighting, it seems close to
impossible for one individual to adequately evaluate the integration of each
component. Musical theorist Joseph Swain has made remarkable contributions to
characterizing the dramatic role of music in a number of significant musical
comedies. In the process, Swain increases the respect due composers (and, possibly,
arrangers) for their dramatic sense. For example, his explanation of the
significance of Leonard Bernstein’s music for the pervasive dramatic impact of West Side Story makes plain that which
the non-musicians among us have only intuitively experienced. Much of Swain’s
studies achieve remarkable insights into the three components: together they
modify the setting, advance the plot, and flesh-out otherwise sparsely defined
character.
Nevertheless, Swain, perhaps because he focuses on only the
surface dramatic effect, expresses doubts about the function of other elements
which uses the music, such as dance, particularly the ground-breaking ballet
sequence in Oklahoma ! He questions the appropriateness of the music which accompanies
the Laurey-makes-up-her-mind ballet at the end of the first act of Oklahoma ! Is there some dissonance in the great
initial triumph of Rodgers and Hammerstein? Has Swain found a pocket of
inconsistency in Oklahoma !? He suggests that Rodgers was looking the other way while the
ballet was constructed. But, assume that the ballet, whatever its superficial
dissonance, is essential to understanding the whole of the play. Further, by
applying this approach to other creative efforts, perhaps an improved insight
into the human creative process might happen.
From the Hollywood perspective on
musical theater, three thousand miles west of Broadway, the show was the thing,
at least from the Thirties into the Fifties (Judy Garland/Mickey Rooney’s “Let’s
put on a show", through Fred Astaire’s Bandwagon
and Gene Kelly’s Singin’ in the Rain).
The “show” not “play” is the world everyone wants to be in. Even for Broadway in
the Seventies (Michael Bennett’s A Chorus
Line) and and London ’s West
End in the Eighties (Andrew Lloyd Webber’s Phantom of the Opera), the stage is still a metaphor for the “real”
world.
Fully one-half of Lerner’s autobiography is devoted to My Fair Lady. As with so many
professionals, the seeming center of the person’s life is his or her great
public success. James Watson’s principal personal and public publication is solely concerned with the construction of the
DNA molecule model, colored by anecdotes and human frailties. Even Francis
Crick’s memoirs can’t help but climax halfway through with their joint DNA
triumph.
If the play is the thing and all the world is a stage (the
idea is hardly original here), isn’t it also true for any creative person that
his or her passion, however circumscribed and inaccessible it may be to the
non-specialist, is their own world, their own personal stage? And, where is
that stage: Cambridge , Broadway, Hollywood , Bloomington , Washington , or Arvada ?
Is it a place at all? And what roles do other persons play on the personal
stage: what about collaboration?
Would My Fair Lady
have successfully emerged without any one of the principals: Lerner, Loewe,
Moss Hart, Rex Harrison, or Julie Andrews (never mind Shaw or the Greeks)? Oklahoma ! without Rodgers, Hammerstein, or Agnes
deMille (again, disregarding original playwright Lynn Riggs)? And what about
that most fickle and determinative collaborator: the audience? Commercial
success seems to be a prerequisite to artistic success in musical theater,
perhaps more than any other of the arts, if only because of the high cost of a
musical production. If musical comedies are not successful the first time, they
tend to disappear, seldom to be rediscovered a decade or two later. In contrast,
a Leonard Bernstein can almost single-handedly “make” Gustav Mahler a master, decades
after his death. Has anyone successfully resurrected any musical play which failed
to find an audience collaborator? Even some Hollywood
drama classics may have originally failed in the box office: Citizen Kane and It’s a Wonderful Life didn’t light up the sky when first released. Now
the former is almost always included in critics’ Top Tens, and the latter is
viewed as Frank Capra’s masterpiece (personally, I prefer his first big commercial
and critical success It Happened One
Night). On the literary side, Flannery O’Connor was always deeply troubled
by the sparse sales of Wise Blood
despite its critical success; alas, its nearly universal subsequent inclusion
in college freshmen curricula (in the mid-1960s at least) occurred after her
untimely death.
Curiously, then, musical comedy seems to require active “collaboration”
with the audience in such a way that virtually no other art form requires. In a
sense, musical comedy has something in common with science, because science is
intrinsically collaborative. Even the solitary researcher ultimately submits
results for publication requiring peer review, a kind of “anonymous” collaboration.
The research itself builds on the contributions of others, and the resulting
article is to an extent tailored to a particular audience of professionals in
the same or related disciplines. The team research efforts of “big science” are
now all well known. Since the Manhattan Project of the Second World War, large
groups of scientific researchers have become the rule, for both basic and
applied science. The aborted Super-Conducting Super-Collider south of Dallas is one of a long
line of such ventures.
Popular scientific literature represents a mix of attempts
to convey non-technical understanding of contemporary scientific theory, models,
practice, and (particularly beginning with Watson’s Double Helix) anecdotal accounts of scientific discoveries and/or
careers. Significant attention has been paid to the importance of collaboration
and interaction among scientists in many such accounts. Nevertheless, there has
been significant effort to attempt to understand the nature of scientific
progress. Thomas Kuhn’s Structure of
Scientific Revolutions has been readily embraced by many active scientists
themselves; an excellent example from my own field of geology and geophysics is
the commentary which accompanies the late (Stanford geophysicist) Allan Cox’s
compilation of milestone contributions to the development of plate tectonics
and recognition of magnetic field reversals. Kuhn’s distinction between normal
and crisis science has found some resonance in the experience of many
scientists who survived the “fixed versus drifting continents” crisis and
subsequent plate tectonic revolution.
Karl Popper’s theory of scientific progress (concisely, if
somewhat inexactly states that science progresses by advancement of hypotheses
as a result of experimental or logical falsification of prior hypotheses; thus
only testable hypotheses can be admitted to scientific respectability) has been
popular among some philosophers of science. But, recently, Popperian approaches
(which also imply the existence of objective falsification methodology – for
example classical statistics) have been undermined by Bayesian philosophers, who
argue for the primacy of the initial subjective inference and its progressive
confirmation or denial. Subjectivity, some Bayesians contend, is inherent even
in the supposedly objective assumptions of classical statistics. The
exploitation of Bayesian inference and its cryptic role in science seems to be
a particularly stimulating area for future investigation, along the lines developed
by Edwin Jaynes, for example; Jaynes seemed to suggest that scientists, indeed all
rational human decision-makers, are actually unconscious Bayesians in the way
in which they solve problems.
The essence of Bayesian inference is the incorporation of
prior experience into hypothesis formulation and testing. Prior experience involves
experiment, observation and interaction, any of which may be disciplined,
undisciplined, or capricious. The great trepidation of scientists in general
and classical statisticians, as well, has been fear of subjective bias, which
might color not only the hypothesis formulation, but also hypothesis testing. British
Bayesians Howson and Urbach argue that bias is unavoidable, and, as such,
should not only be acknowledged, but exploited. A particular mathematical
theorem advanced by an Eighteenth-Century clergyman, Thomas Bayes (in l763), provides
the means by which this prior experience (after all, one person’s “experience” can
be another person’s “bias”) is explicitly incorporated into and evaluated as
part of the decision-making process.
This book is an attempt to apply seemingly esoteric inferential
logic to human creativity. The most important point I wish to make is that
subjectivity does indeed play an essential role in science, not merely because
scientists are fallible, but because all the knowledge of the universe or any part
of the universe necessary for complete understanding cannot possibly be obtained.
Therefore, inference based on inadequate information is always required. And,
in its genesis, inference is subjective.
The intrinsic subjectivity of the arts has never been in dispute,
but it may come as some surprise to the uninitiated that science has an
essential subjective component as well. The subjectivity, to reiterate, is not
merely inherent in the humanity of the scientist, but in the formulation of
possible problem solutions, in their execution, and even recognition and selection
of the problems themselves.
I recall some time ago, a recruiting video was being prepared
by a university college of science, for encouraging high school students to
consider a scientific career, especially at that university and college. One of
those interviewed for the video was a distinguished professor who occupied an endowed
chair in the chemistry department: “We are the new high priests of society,” he
told the anonymous interviewer and, through him, the potential scientists of
tomorrow. Another professor, from a different department, wrote a note to the
dean objecting to the endowed chair’s comments, and observed that no one was
making sacrifices on altars in his department; his department didn’t have
altars, although he couldn’t vouch for what was going on in chemistry.
Nevertheless, the almost conscious identification of contemporary science with
ancient religion, made by that professor, isn’t necessarily that far off the
mark.
The most subjective and creative of human endeavors often
has religious overtones. Jung saw significant foreshadowing of his own theories
in the work of the German poets Goethe and Schilling, particular the former’s Faust, a reworking of the Old Testament Job
story with a profoundly different twist. The medieval precursors of science were
the alchemists and astrologers, many of whom were clerics who mixed heretical
theologies into their cauldrons of myth and futility. The performing arts in
the Middle Ages centered on Passion plays in song, out of which opera emerged.
Liturgy has much in common with the formality of experimental science and the
structure of theatrical performance. To the untrained, science can seem
esoteric and mysterious, rather like the Gnostic mystery sects of the first few
centuries. But, is it the formality of science that is so mysterious, or its
requirement of rigorous initiation by intensive training, or is the mystery in
the creative urge that seems to motivate the scientific process?
In an effort to explore these questions further, it might be
worthwhile to consider the flip side of creativity. One can speculate about the
how and why of Lerner and Loewe’s My Fair
Lady and Crick and Watson’s DNA model, but what about the meaning of each
to its respective audience? Since the total audience for a successful Broadway
musical is larger than that of a scientific theory (although the eventual
social importance of each might well be reversed), and success of the musical
is dependent on that audience, they are, in effect, essential collaborators in
musical theater. This is extended further by considering the creative
contribution the audience makes. Isn’t there a kind of creativity involved in
the reception of a work of art that complements the initial creativity of its
production? And, if we can acquire some insight into this creative response, maybe
this can be used as a basis of consideration of the creative effort involved in
genesis of the product.
The biographical accounts of the process of play-making leave
the distinct impression that the critical steps in the creative, productive
process are interactive. What Alan said to Fritz; how Richard dealt with Larry;
Moss made this suggestion… But, to reiterate, even in the most intense collaboration,
the ideas, verse, and notes emerge from individual human imagination, memory, and
reason. So it is that the response of the listener and viewer is largely internal,
affected and effected, certainly by the subtle collective physical response of
the rest of the audience. The individual response is in essence internal. The
senses feel the perception of light, movement, color, sound, ambience, and smell
in the brain, where the real stage or screen is. For each member of the
audience, My Fair Lady happens in his
or her own consciousness and, perhaps, unconsciousness.
The distinctive characters played by flesh-and-blood actors whose
own personalities may be different from the characters played, are,
nevertheless, real to the audience person, insofar as response is concerned. The
reality is in interpreting the response of the individual to a particular play
or motion picture; it may assumed that the meaning is grasped to the extent
that each character finds identity with a part of oneself; the relationships of
characters also find reflection in internal dialogues, and the whole of the
story (inadequately and grossly, of course) approximates the whole of the
person. To the person, then, Henry Higgins is not Rex Harrison; Professor
Higgins is part of oneself. Eliza Doolittle is not Julie Andrews or Audrey
Hepburn or Marni Nixon; she also is part of the individual, as are Alfred
Doolittle, Colonel Pickering, or even Freddie-Eynesford-Hill.
The second assumption has to do with the dramatic content of
the play. The fully satisfying play is itself, by definition, fulfilling. As the
postulates of a theorem imply its conclusion, the fullness of the (complete) play
is implicit in its parts. The music of the best of plays not only serves and advances
the plot, it expresses it. The portents of chance impel the change; the consequence
is in a sense its own cause. The medium is the message.
The third assumption is that the response of the audience
produced by the inner drama of the individual in its own way shapes the play. The
play is its own cause and consequence. The concepts of inner characters and
interior dramas can be an alien idea in approaching the performing arts in particular
and human creativity in general. They may not be self-evident, without a little
imaginative work. Viewing the concepts as hypothetical may sound quasi-scientific.
But, for the individual encountering these ideas for the first time, perhaps he
or she could view himself or herself as a kind of laboratory.
Histories of American musical theater emphasize the growth
of musical comedy out of the European operetta, as well as American folk and
African-American spiritual and jazz forms. Typically, the musical play of the
first few decades of the Twentieth Century was more of a revue, with a very
thin plot line supposedly connecting otherwise unrelated song-and-dance routines.
Typically, such revues incorporated songs by several different composers and
lyricists, who had little to do with the overall form of the play. Kern and Hammerstein’s
Showboat (1927) is usually recognized
as the pioneer of a new form.
Storyline and music were integrated, to a great extent. Thus, some of the music
of the play, instead of providing an entertaining interlude, was actually
designed to advance the plot. The very setting of Showboat, however, provides the backdrop for apparent interludes,
since the principal characters are explicit performers aboard a floating
theater (hmm, interesting stage, that).
With Oklahoma !, however, the vision of a fully-integrated
musical play was most completely achieved; it is difficult to point to any
other play, before or after, which is its match. By the addition of Western
ballet, virtually every part of the play is connected; there are no isolated interludes.
Some standard “dramatic” elements still remain: there are the primary love
triangle of Curly-Laurey-Jud and the secondary triangle of Ado
Annie-Will-Hakeem. Parallel love stories are common in other musicals after Oklahoma !: Carousel, South Pacific, West Side Story, and Music
Man. Lerner felt he and Loewe were breaking new ground in My Fair Lady’s absence of obvious
subplot, represented by a secondary love story. However, the common assumption
made by so many stage historians is that the subplot represents a kind of
convention, for example, “comic relief.” Stephen Sondheim said that the purpose
of “Send in the clowns” in A Little Night
Music is to express the recognition by the female protagonist (herself a
stage performer) that the plot is getting too heavy; it is time for comic
relief. The character and the creators of the play see the apparent need for a
change of tone and pace, and for the principal characters to change costumes.
Certainly, traditional forms of the performing arts, by the
very fact of their tradition are to be dealt with by adapting, adopting, or
even rejecting them (although rejection might mean a mirror image of the
spurned ingredient is the replacement). But it might be worthwhile to consider
the possibility that subplot has a deeper function than that of providing
relief, a break, or new garb.
[Some of the articles which follow were originally posted on maxfrac; a few edits and observations have been added.]
No comments:
Post a Comment